Logo Passei Direto

Reading6-3-Myers6-28

User badge image

Sent by Renato Fonseca in

Study with thousands of resources!

Text Material Preview

Reading 6.3 
Causes of Conflict 
 
Source: Module 28 (pages 355-368) of Myers, D. G. (2012). 
Exploring social psychology (6th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. 
 
 
 
 
 
Social Psychology 
Professor Scott Plous 
Wesleyan University 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
Note: This reading material is being provided free of charge to Coursera 
students through the generosity of David G. Myers and McGraw-Hill, all 
rights reserved. Unauthorized duplication, sales, or distribution of this 
work is strictly forbidden and makes it less likely that publishers and 
authors will freely share materials in the future, so please respect the 
spirit of open education by limiting your use to this course. 
355
MODULE
28
❖
Causes of Conflict
There is a speech that has been spoken in many languages by the 
leaders of many countries. It goes like this: “The intentions of our 
country are entirely peaceful. Yet, we are also aware that other 
nations, with their new weapons, threaten us. Thus we must defend 
ourselves against attack. By so doing, we shall protect our way of life 
and preserve the peace” (Richardson, 1960). Almost every nation claims 
concern only for peace but, mistrusting other nations, arms itself in self-
defense. The result is a world that has been spending $2 billion per day 
on arms and armies while hundreds of millions die of malnutrition and 
untreated disease.
 The elements of such conflict (a perceived incompatibility of actions 
or goals) are similar at many levels: conflict between nations in an arms 
race, between religious factions disputing points of doctrine, between 
corporate executives and workers disputing salaries, and between bick-
ering spouses. Let’s consider these conflict elements.
SOCIAL DILEMMAS
Several of the problems that most threaten our human future—nuclear 
arms, climate change, overpopulation, natural-resource depletion—arise 
as various parties pursue their self-interests, ironically, to their collective 
detriment. One individual may think, “It would cost me a lot to buy 
expensive greenhouse emission controls. Besides, the greenhouse gases 
I personally generate are trivial.” Many others reason similarly, and the 
result is a warming climate, rising seas, and more extreme weather.
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 355 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 355 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
356 PART FOUR SOCIAL RELATIONS
 Thus, choices that are individually rewarding become collectively 
punishing. We therefore have a dilemma: How can we reconcile indi-
vidual self-interest with communal well-being?
 To isolate and study that dilemma, social psychologists have used 
laboratory games that expose the heart of many real social conflicts. 
“Social psychologists who study conflict are in much the same position 
as the astronomers,” noted conflict researcher Morton Deutsch (1999). 
“We cannot conduct true experiments with large-scale social events. But 
we can identify the conceptual similarities between the large scale and 
the small, as the astronomers have between the planets and Newton’s 
apple. That is why the games people play as subjects in our laboratory 
may advance our understanding of war, peace, and social justice.”
 Let’s consider two laboratory games that are each an example of a 
social trap: the Prisoner’s Dilemma and the Tragedy of the Commons.
The Prisoner’s Dilemma
This dilemma derives from an anecdote concerning two suspects being 
questioned separately by a district attorney (DA) (Rapoport, 1960). The 
DA knows they are jointly guilty but has only enough evidence to con-
vict them of a lesser offense. So the DA creates an incentive for each one 
to confess privately:
• If Prisoner A confesses and Prisoner B doesn’t, the DA will 
grant immunity to A, and will use A’s confession to convict B 
of a maximum offense (and vice versa if B confesses and A 
doesn’t).
• If both confess, each will receive a moderate sentence.
• If neither prisoner confesses, each will be convicted of a lesser 
crime and receive a light sentence.
The matrix of Figure 28-1 summarizes the choices. If you were a prisoner 
faced with such a dilemma, with no chance to talk to the other prisoner, 
would you confess?
 Many people say they would confess to be granted immunity, even 
though mutual nonconfession elicits lighter sentences than mutual con-
fession. Perhaps this is because (as shown in the Figure 28-1 matrix) no 
matter what the other prisoner decides, each is better off confessing than 
being convicted individually. If the other also confesses, the sentence is 
moderate rather than severe. If the other does not confess, one goes free.
 In some 2,000 studies (Dawes, 1991), university students have faced 
variations of the Prisoner’s Dilemma with the choices being to defect or 
to cooperate, and the outcomes not being prison terms but chips, money, 
or course points. On any given decision, a person is better off defecting 
w
w
w
.m
hh
e.com/myersesp
6e 
Activity
28.1
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 356 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 356 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
 MODULE 28 CAUSES OF CONFLICT 357
(because such behavior exploits the other’s cooperation or protects 
against the other’s exploitation). However—and here’s the rub—by not 
cooperating, both parties end up far worse off than if they had trusted 
each other and thus had gained a joint profit. This dilemma often traps 
each one in a maddening predicament in which both realize they could 
mutually profit. But unable to communicate and mistrusting each other, 
they often become “locked in” to not cooperating.
 Punishing another’s lack of cooperation might seem like a smart 
strategy, but in the laboratory it can have counterproductive effects 
(Dreber & others, 2008). Punishment typically triggers retaliation, which 
means that those who punish tend to escalate conflict, worsening their 
outcomes, while nice guys finish first. What punishers see as a defensive 
reaction, recipients see as an aggressive escalation (Anderson & others, 
2008). When hitting back, they may hit harder while seeing themselves 
as merely returning tit for tat. In one experiment, London volunteers 
used a mechanical device to press back on another’s finger after receiv-
ing pressure on their own. While seeking to reciprocate with the same 
Confesses
Doesn’t
confess
5 years 0 years
0 years 1 year
5 years 10 years
10 years 1 year
Confesses
Doesn’t
confess
Prisoner B
Prisoner A
FIGURE 28-1
The classic Prisoner’s Dilemma. In each box, the number 
above the diagonal is prisoner A’s outcome. Thus, if both 
prisoners confess, both get five years. If neither confesses, each 
gets a year. If one confesses, that prisoner is set free in exchange 
for evidence used to convict the other of a crime bringing a 
10-year sentence. If you were one of the prisoners, unable to 
communicate with your fellow prisoner, would you confess?
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 357 13/12/10 11:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 357 13/12/10 11:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
358 PART FOUR SOCIAL RELATIONS
degree of pressure, they typically responded with 40 percent more force. 
Thus, touches soon escalated to hard presses, much like a child saying 
“I just touched him, and then he hit me!” (Shergill & others, 2003).
The Tragedy of the Commons
Many social dilemmas involve more than two parties. Global warming 
stems from deforestation and from the carbon dioxide emitted by cars, 
furnaces, and coal-fired power plants. Each gas-guzzling SUV contrib-
utes infinitesimally to the problem, and the harm each does is diffused 
over many people.To model such social predicaments, researchers have 
developed laboratory dilemmas that involve multiple people.
 A metaphor for the insidious nature of social dilemmas is what ecol-
ogist Garrett Hardin (1968) called the Tragedy of the Commons. He 
derived the name from the centrally located grassy pasture in old Eng-
lish towns.
 In today’s world the “commons” can be air, water, fish, cookies, or 
any shared and limited resource. If all use the resource in moderation, 
it may replenish itself as rapidly as it’s harvested. The grass will grow, 
the fish will reproduce, and the cookie jar will be restocked. If not, there 
occurs a tragedy of the commons. Imagine 100 farmers surrounding a 
commons capable of sustaining 100 cows. When each grazes one cow, 
the common feeding ground is optimally used. But then a farmer rea-
sons, “If I put a second cow in the pasture, I’ll double my output, minus 
the mere 1 percent overgrazing” and adds a second cow. So does each of 
the other farmers. The inevitable result? The Tragedy of the Commons—
a mud field.
 Likewise, environmental pollution is the sum of many minor pollu-
tions, each of which benefits the individual polluters much more than 
they could benefit themselves (and the environment) if they stopped 
polluting. We litter public places—dorm lounges, parks, zoos—while 
keeping our personal spaces clean. We deplete our natural resources 
because the immediate personal benefits of, say, taking a long, hot 
shower outweigh the seemingly inconsequential costs. Whalers knew 
others would exploit the whales if they didn’t and that taking a few 
whales would hardly diminish the species. Therein lies the tragedy. 
Everybody’s business (conservation) becomes nobody’s business.
 Is such individualism uniquely American? Kaori Sato (1987) gave 
students in a more collective culture, Japan, opportunities to harvest—
for actual money—trees from a simulated forest. The students shared 
equally the costs of planting the forest, and the result was like those in 
Western cultures. More than half the trees were harvested before they 
had grown to the most profitable size.
 Sato’s forest reminds me of our home’s cookie jar, which was 
restocked once a week. What we should have done was conserve cookies 
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 358 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 358 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
 MODULE 28 CAUSES OF CONFLICT 359
so that each day we could each enjoy two or three. But lacking regula-
tion and fearing that other family members would soon deplete the 
resource, what we actually did was maximize our individual cookie 
consumption by downing one after the other. The result: Within 
24 hours the cookie glut would end, the jar sitting empty for the rest 
of the week.
 The Prisoner’s Dilemma and the Tragedy of the Commons games have 
several similar features. First, both games tempt people to explain their own 
behavior situationally (“I had to protect myself against exploitation by my 
opponent”) and to explain their partners’ behavior dispositionally (“she 
was greedy,” “he was untrustworthy”). Most never realize that their coun-
terparts are viewing them with the same fundamental attribution error 
(Gifford & Hine, 1997; Hine & Gifford, 1996). People with self-inflating, 
self-focused narcissistic tendencies are especially unlikely to empathize 
with others’ perspectives (Campbell & others, 2005).
 Second, motives often change. At first, people are eager to make some 
easy money, then to minimize their losses, and finally to save face and 
avoid defeat (Brockner & others, 1982; Teger, 1980). These shifting 
motives are strikingly similar to the shifting motives during the buildup 
of the 1960s Vietnam war. At first, President Johnson’s speeches expressed 
concern for democracy, freedom, and justice. As the conflict escalated, 
his concern became protecting America’s honor and avoiding the national 
humiliation of losing a war. A similar shift occurred during the war in 
Iraq, which was initially proposed as a response to supposed weapons 
of mass destruction.
 Third, most real-life conflicts, like the Prisoner’s Dilemma and the 
Tragedy of the Commons, are non-zero-sum games. The two sides’ prof-
its and losses need not add up to zero. Both can win; both can lose. Each 
game pits the immediate interests of individuals against the well-being 
of the group. Each is a diabolical social trap that shows how, even when 
each individual behaves “rationally,” harm can result. No malicious per-
son planned for the earth’s atmosphere to be warmed by a blanket of 
carbon dioxide.
 Not all self-serving behavior leads to collective doom. In a plentiful 
commons—as in the world of the eighteenth-century capitalist economist 
Adam Smith (1776, p. 18)—individuals who seek to maximize their own 
profit may also give the community what it needs: “It is not from the 
benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our 
dinner,” he observed, “but from their regard to their own interest.”
Resolving Social Dilemmas
Faced with social traps, how can we induce people to cooperate for their 
mutual betterment? Research with the laboratory dilemmas reveals sev-
eral ways (Gifford & Hine, 1997).
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 359 10/12/10 1:43 PM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 359 10/12/10 1:43 PM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
360 PART FOUR SOCIAL RELATIONS
Regulation
If taxes were entirely voluntary, how many would pay their full share? 
Modern societies do not depend on charity to pay for schools, parks, and 
social and military security. We also develop rules to safeguard our com-
mon good. Fishing and hunting have long been regulated by local 
seasons and limits; at the global level, an International Whaling Com-
mission sets an agreed-upon “harvest” that enables whales to regenerate. 
Likewise, where fishing industries, such as the Alaskan halibut fishery, 
have implemented “catch shares”—guaranteeing each fisher a percent-
age of each year’s allowable catch—competition and overfishing have 
been greatly reduced (Costello & others, 2008).
Small Is Beautiful
There is another way to resolve social dilemmas: Make the group small. 
In a small commons, each person feels more responsible and effective 
(Kerr, 1989). As a group grows larger, people become more likely to 
think, “I couldn’t have made a difference anyway”—a common excuse 
for noncooperation (Kerr & Kaufman-Gilliland, 1997).
 In small groups, people also feel more identified with a group’s suc-
cess. Anything else that enhances group identity will also increase coop-
eration. Even just a few minutes of discussion or just believing that one 
shares similarities with others in the group can increase “we feeling” and 
cooperation (Brewer, 1987; Orbell & others, 1988). Residential stability 
also strengthens communal identity and procommunity behavior, includ-
ing even baseball game attendance independent of a team’s record (Oishi 
& others, 2007).
 On the Pacific Northwest island where I grew up, our small neigh-
borhood shared a communal water supply. On hot summer days when 
the reservoir ran low, a light came on, signaling our 15 families to con-
serve. Recognizing our responsibility to one another, and feeling that our 
conservation really mattered, each of us conserved. Never did the reser-
voir run dry. In a much larger commons—say, a city—voluntary conser-
vation is less successful.
Communication
To resolve a social dilemma, people must communicate. In the laboratory 
as in real life, group communication sometimes degenerates into threats 
and name-calling (Deutsch & Krauss, 1960). More often, communication 
enables people to cooperate (Bornstein & others, 1988, 1989). Discussing 
the dilemma forges a group identity, whichenhances concern for every-
one’s welfare. It devises group norms and consensus expectations and 
puts pressure on members to follow them. Especially when people are 
face-to-face, it enables them to commit themselves to cooperation (Bouas 
& Komorita, 1996; Drolet & Morris, 2000; Kerr & others, 1994, 1997; 
Pruitt, 1998).
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 360 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 360 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
 MODULE 28 CAUSES OF CONFLICT 361
 Without communication, those who expect others not to cooperate 
will usually refuse to cooperate themselves (Messé & Sivacek, 1979; 
Pruitt & Kimmel, 1977). One who mistrusts is almost sure to be uncoop-
erative (to protect against exploitation). Noncooperation, in turn, feeds 
further mistrust (“What else could I do? It’s a dog-eat-dog world”). In 
experiments, communication reduces mistrust, enabling people to reach 
agreements that lead to their common betterment.
Changing the Payoffs
Laboratory cooperation rises when experimenters change the payoff 
matrix to reward cooperation and punish exploitation (Komorita & 
Barth, 1985; Pruitt & Rubin, 1986). Changing payoffs also helps resolve 
actual dilemmas. In some cities, freeways clog and skies smog because 
people prefer the convenience of driving themselves directly to work. 
Each knows that one more car does not add noticeably to the congestion 
and pollution. To alter the personal cost-benefit calculations, many cities 
now give carpoolers incentives, such as designated freeway lanes or 
reduced tolls.
Appeals to Altruistic Norms
When cooperation obviously serves the public good, one can usefully 
appeal to the social-responsibility norm (Lynn & Oldenquist, 1986). 
For example, if people believe public transportation saves time, they 
will be more likely to use it if they also believe it reduces pollution 
(Van Vugt & others, 1996). In the 1960s struggle for civil rights, many 
marchers willingly agreed, for the sake of the larger group, to suffer 
harassment, beatings, and jail. In wartime, people make great per-
sonal sacrifices for the good of their group. As Winston Churchill 
said of the Battle of Britain, the actions of the Royal Air Force pilots 
were genuinely altruistic: A great many people owed a great deal to 
those who flew into battle knowing there was a high probability—70 
percent for those on a standard tour of duty—that they would not 
return (Levinson, 1950).
 To summarize, we can minimize destructive entrapment in social 
dilemmas by establishing rules that regulate self-serving behavior, by 
keeping groups small, by enabling people to communicate, by changing 
payoffs to make cooperation more rewarding, and by invoking compel-
ling altruistic norms.
COMPETITION
In Module 28 (Causes of Conflict), we noted that racial hostilities often 
arise when groups compete for scarce jobs, housing, or resources. When 
interests clash, conflict erupts.
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 361 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 361 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
362 PART FOUR SOCIAL RELATIONS
 But does competition by itself provoke hostile conflict? Real-life 
situations are so complex that it is hard to be sure. If competition is 
indeed responsible, then it should be possible to provoke in an experi-
ment. We could randomly divide people into two groups, have the 
groups compete for a scarce resource, and note what happens. That is 
precisely what Muzafer Sherif (1966) and his colleagues did in a dramatic 
series of experiments with typical 11- and 12-year-old boys. The inspira-
tion for those experiments dated back to Sherif’s witnessing, as a teen-
ager, Greek troops invading his Turkish province in 1919.
They started killing people right and left. [That] made a great impression 
on me. There and then I became interested in understanding why these 
things were happening among human beings. . . . I wanted to learn what-
ever science or specialization was needed to understand this intergroup 
savagery. (Quoted by Aron & Aron, 1989, p. 131.)
 After studying the social roots of savagery, Sherif introduced the 
seeming essentials into several three-week summer camping experi-
ences. In one such study, he divided 22 unacquainted Oklahoma City 
boys into two groups, took them to a Boy Scout camp in separate buses, 
and settled them in bunkhouses about a half-mile apart at Oklahoma’s 
Robber’s Cave State Park. For most of the first week, each group was 
unaware of the other’s existence. By cooperating in various activities—
preparing meals, camping out, fixing up a swimming hole, building a 
rope bridge—each group soon became close-knit. They gave themselves 
names: “Rattlers” and “Eagles.” Typifying the good feeling, a sign 
appeared in one cabin: “Home Sweet Home.”
 Group identity thus established, the stage was set for the conflict. 
Near the first week’s end, the Rattlers discovered the Eagles “on ‘our’ 
baseball field.” When the camp staff then proposed a tournament of 
competitive activities between the two groups (baseball games, tugs-of-
war, cabin inspections, treasure hunts, and so forth), both groups 
responded enthusiastically. This was win-lose competition. The spoils 
(medals, knives) would all go to the tournament victor.
 The result? The camp gradually degenerated into open warfare. It was 
like a scene from William Golding’s novel Lord of the Flies, which depicts 
the social disintegration of boys marooned on an island. In Sherif’s study, 
the conflict began with each side calling the other names during the com-
petitive activities. Soon it escalated to dining hall “garbage wars,” flag 
burnings, cabin ransackings, even fistfights. Asked to describe the other 
group, the boys said they were “sneaky,” “smart alecks,” “stinkers,” but 
referring to their own group as “brave,” “tough,” “friendly.”
 The win-lose competition had produced intense conflict, negative 
images of the outgroup, and strong ingroup cohesiveness and pride. Group 
polarization no doubt exacerbated the conflict. In competition-fostering 
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 362 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 362 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
 MODULE 28 CAUSES OF CONFLICT 363
situations, groups behave more competitively than do individuals (Wild-
schut & others, 2003, 2007). Men, especially, get caught up in intergroup 
competition (Van Vugt & others, 2007).
 All of this occurred without any cultural, physical, or economic 
 differences between the two groups and with boys who were their 
 communities’ “cream of the crop.” Sherif noted that, had we visited the 
camp at that point, we would have concluded these “were wicked, 
d isturbed, and vicious bunches of youngsters” (1966, p. 85). Actually, 
their evil behavior was triggered by an evil situation. Fortunately, as 
we will see in Module 29, Sherif not only made strangers into enemies; 
he then also made the enemies into friends.
PERCEIVED INJUSTICE
“That’s unfair!” “What a ripoff!” “We deserve better!” Such comments 
typify conflicts bred by perceived injustice. But what is “justice”? Accord-
ing to some social-psychological theorists, people perceive justice as 
equity—the distribution of rewards in proportion to individuals’ contri-
butions (Walster & others, 1978). If you and I have a relationship 
(employer-employee, teacher-student, husband-wife, colleague-colleague), 
it is equitable if
 My outcomes 
5
 Your outcomes 
My inputs Your inputs 
If you contribute more and benefit less than I do, you will feel exploited 
and irritated; I may feel exploitative and guilty. Chances are, though,that 
you will be more sensitive to the inequity than I will (Greenberg, 1986; 
Messick & Sentis, 1979).
 We may agree with the equity principle’s definition of justice yet 
disagree on whether our relationship is equitable. If two people are col-
leagues, what will each consider a relevant input? The one who is older 
may favor basing pay on seniority, the other on current productivity. 
Given such a disagreement, whose definition is likely to prevail? More 
often than not, those with social power convince themselves and others 
that they deserve what they’re getting (Mikula, 1984). This has been 
called a “golden” rule: Whoever has the gold makes the rules.
 And how do those who are exploited react? Elaine Hatfield, William 
Walster, and Ellen Berscheid (1978) detected three possibilities. They can 
accept and justify their inferior position (“We’re poor but we’re happy”). 
They can demand compensation, perhaps by harassing, embarrassing, even 
cheating their exploiter. If all else fails, they may try to restore equity by 
retaliating.
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 363 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 363 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
364 PART FOUR SOCIAL RELATIONS
MISPERCEPTION
Recall that conflict is a perceived incompatibility of actions or goals. 
Many conflicts contain but a small core of truly incompatible goals; the 
bigger problem is the misperceptions of the other’s motives and goals. 
The Eagles and the Rattlers did indeed have some genuinely incompat-
ible aims. But their perceptions subjectively magnified their differences 
(Figure 28-2).
 In earlier modules we considered the seeds of such misperception. 
The self-serving bias leads individuals and groups to accept credit for 
their good deeds and shirk responsibility for bad deeds, without 
according others the same benefit of the doubt. A tendency to self-
justify inclines people to deny the wrong of their evil acts (“You call 
that hitting? I hardly touched him!”). Thanks to the fundamental attri-
bution error, each side sees the other’s hostility as reflecting an evil 
disposition. One then filters the information and interprets it to fit 
one’s preconceptions. Groups frequently polarize these self-serving, self-
justifying, biasing tendencies. One symptom of groupthink is the ten-
dency to perceive one’s own group as moral and strong, the opposi-
tion as evil and weak. Acts of terrorism that in most people’s eyes are 
despicable brutality are seen by others as “holy war.” Indeed, the 
mere fact of being in a group triggers an ingroup bias. And negative 
stereotypes of the outgroup, once formed, are often resistant to contra-
dictory evidence.
 So it should not surprise us, though it should sober us, to discover 
that people in conflict form distorted images of one another. Even the 
types of misperception are intriguingly predictable.
Misperceptions
True
incompatibility
FIGURE 28-2
Many conflicts contain a core of truly 
incompatible goals surrounded by a 
larger exterior of misperceptions.
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 364 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 364 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
 MODULE 28 CAUSES OF CONFLICT 365
Mirror-Image Perceptions
To a striking degree, the misperceptions of those in conflict are mutual. 
People in conflict attribute similar virtues to themselves and vices to the 
other. When the American psychologist Urie Bronfenbrenner (1961) visited 
the Soviet Union in 1960 and conversed with many ordinary citizens in 
Russian, he was astonished to hear them saying the same things about 
America that Americans were saying about Russia. The Russians said that 
the U.S. government was militarily aggressive; that it exploited and 
deluded the American people; that in diplomacy it was not to be trusted. 
“Slowly and painfully, it forced itself upon one that the Russians’ distorted 
picture of us was curiously similar to our view of them—a mirror image.”
 When two sides have clashing perceptions, at least one of the two is 
misperceiving the other. And when such misperceptions exist, noted 
Bronfenbrenner, “It is a psychological phenomenon without parallel in 
the gravity of its consequences . . . for it is characteristic of such images that 
they are self-confirming.” If A expects B to be hostile, A may treat B in such 
a way that B fulfills A’s expectations, thus beginning a vicious circle 
(Kennedy & Pronin, 2008). Morton Deutsch (1986) explained:
You hear the false rumor that a friend is saying nasty things about you; 
you snub him; he then badmouths you, confirming your expectation. 
Similarly, if the policymakers of East and West believe that war is likely 
and either attempts to increase its military security vis-à-vis the other, the 
other’s response will justify the initial move.
Negative mirror-image perceptions have been an obstacle to peace in 
many places:
• Both sides of the Arab-Israeli conflict insisted that “we” are 
motivated by our need to protect our security and our territory, 
whereas “they” want to obliterate us and gobble up our land. 
“We” are the indigenous people here, “they” are the invaders. 
“We” are the victims; “they” are the aggressors (Bar-Tal, 2004; 
Heradstveit, 1979; Kelmom, 2007). Given such intense mistrust, 
negotiation is difficult.
• At Northern Ireland’s University of Ulster, J. A. Hunter and his 
colleagues (1991) showed Catholic and Protestant students vid-
eos of a Protestant attack at a Catholic funeral and a Catholic 
attack at a Protestant funeral. Most students attributed the other 
side’s attack to “bloodthirsty” motives but its own side’s attack 
to retaliation or self-defense.
• Terrorism is in the eye of the beholder. In the Middle East, a 
public opinion survey found 98 percent of Palestinians agreeing 
that the killing of 29 Palestinians by an assault-rifle-bearing 
Israeli at a mosque constituted terrorism, and 82 percent disagreed 
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 365 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 365 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
366 PART FOUR SOCIAL RELATIONS
that the killing of 21 Israeli youths by a Palestinian suicide-
bombing constituted terrorism (Kruglanski & Fishman, 2006). 
Israelis likewise have responded to violence with intensified 
perceptions of Palestinian evil intent (Bar-Tal, 2004).
 Such conflicts, notes Philip Zimbardo (2004a), engage “a two-category 
world—of good people, like US, and of bad people, like THEM.” “In 
fact,” note Daniel Kahneman and Jonathan Renshon (2007), all the biases 
uncovered in 40 years of psychological research are conducive to war. 
They “incline national leaders to exaggerate the evil intentions of adver-
saries, to misjudge how adversaries perceive them, to be overly sanguine 
when hostilities start, and overly reluctant to make necessary conces-
sions in negotiations.”
 Opposing sides in a conflict tend to exaggerate their differences. On 
issues such as immigration and affirmative action, proponents aren’t as 
liberal and opponents aren’t as conservative as their adversaries suppose 
(Sherman & others, 2003). Opposing sides also tend to have a “bias blind 
spot,” notes Cynthia McPherson Frantz (2006). They see their own 
understandings as not influenced by their liking or disliking for others, 
while seeing those who disagree with them as unfair and biased. More-
over, partisans tend to perceive a rival as especially disagreeing with 
their own core values (Chambers & Melnyk, 2006).
 John Chambers, Robert Baron, and Mary Inman (2006) confirmed 
misperceptions on issues related to abortion and politics. Partisans per-
ceived exaggerated differencesfrom their adversaries, who actually 
agreed with them more often than they supposed. From such exagger-
ated perceptions of the other’s position arise culture wars. Ralph White 
(1996, 1998) reports that the Serbs started the war in Bosnia partly out 
of an exaggerated fear of the relatively secularized Bosnian Muslims, 
whose beliefs they wrongly associated with Middle Eastern Islamic fun-
damentalism and fanatical terrorism. Resolving conflict involves aban-
doning such exaggerated perceptions and coming to understand the 
other’s mind. But that isn’t easy, notes Robert Wright (2003): “Putting 
yourself in the shoes of people who do things you find abhorrent may 
be the hardest moral exercise there is.”
 Destructive mirror-image perceptions also operate in conflicts 
between small groups and between individuals. As we saw in the 
dilemma games, both parties may say, “We want to cooperate. But their 
refusal to cooperate forces us to react defensively.” In a study of execu-
tives, Kenneth Thomas and Louis Pondy (1977) uncovered such attribu-
tions. Asked to describe a significant recent conflict, only 12 percent felt 
the other party was cooperative; 74 percent perceived themselves as 
cooperative. The typical executive explained that he or she had “sug-
gested,” “informed,” and “recommended,” whereas the antagonist had 
“demanded,” “disagreed with everything I said,” and “refused.”
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 366 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 366 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
 MODULE 28 CAUSES OF CONFLICT 367
 Group conflicts are often fueled by an illusion that the enemy’s top 
leaders are evil but their people, though controlled and manipulated, are 
pro-us. This evil-leader–good people perception characterized Americans’ 
and Russians’ views of each other during the Cold War. The United 
States entered the Vietnam war believing that in areas dominated by the 
Communist Vietcong “terrorists,” many of the people were allies-in-
waiting. As suppressed information later revealed, those beliefs were 
mere wishful thinking. In 2003 the United States began the Iraq war 
presuming the existence of “a vast underground network that would rise 
in support of coalition forces to assist security and law enforcement” 
(Phillips, 2003). Alas, the network didn’t materialize, and the resulting 
postwar security vacuum enabled looting, sabotage, persistent attacks on 
American forces, and increasing attacks from an insurgency determined 
to drive Western interests from the country.
Shifting Perceptions
If misperceptions accompany conflict, then they should appear and dis-
appear as conflicts wax and wane. And they do, with startling regularity. 
The same processes that create the enemy’s image can reverse that image 
when the enemy becomes an ally. Thus, the “bloodthirsty, cruel, treach-
erous, buck-toothed little Japs” of World War II soon became—in North 
American minds (Gallup, 1972) and in the media—our “intelligent, hard-
working, self-disciplined, resourceful allies.”
 The Germans, who after two world wars were hated, then admired, 
and then again hated, were once again admired—apparently no longer 
plagued by what earlier was presumed to be cruelty in their national 
character. So long as Iraq was attacking unpopular Iran, even while 
using chemical weapons to massacre its own Kurds, many nations sup-
ported it. Our enemy’s enemy is our friend. When Iraq ended its war 
with Iran and invaded oil-rich Kuwait, Iraq’s behavior suddenly became 
“barbaric.” Images of our enemies change with amazing ease.
 The extent of misperceptions during conflict provides a chilling reminder 
that people need not be insane or abnormally malicious to form these dis-
torted images of their antagonists. When we experience conflict with another 
nation, another group, or simply a roommate or a parent, we readily misper-
ceive our own motives and actions as good and the other’s as evil. And just 
as readily, our antagonists form a mirror-image perception of us.
 So, with the antagonists trapped in a social dilemma, competing for 
scarce resources, or perceiving injustice, the conflict continues until 
something enables both parties to peel away their misperceptions and 
work at reconciling their actual differences. Good advice, then, is this: 
When in conflict, do not assume that the other fails to share your values 
and morality. Rather, compare perceptions, assuming that the other is 
likely perceiving the situation differently.
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 367 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 367 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles
368 PART FOUR SOCIAL RELATIONS
CONCEPTS TO REMEMBER
conflict A perceived incompatibil-
ity of actions or goals.
social trap A situation in which 
the conflicting parties, by 
each rationally pursuing its 
self-interest, become caught in 
mutually destructive behavior. 
Examples include the Prisoner’s 
Dilemma and the Tragedy of 
the Commons.
non-zero-sum games Games in 
which outcomes need not sum 
to zero. With cooperation, both 
can win; with competition, 
both can lose. (Also called 
mixed-motive situations.)
mirror-image perceptions Reciprocal 
views of each other often 
held by parties in conflict; for 
example, each may view itself 
as moral and peace-loving and 
the other as evil and aggressive.
mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 368 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494mye35171_ch28_355-368.indd Page 368 08/12/10 4:19 AM user-f494/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles/208/MHSF219/myr35171_disk1of1/0078035171/myr35171_pagefiles

More content from this subject

More content from this subject